The
Contradictions of Black Gentrification as Black Solidarity
Mary Pattillo argues
in Black on the Block: The
Politics of Race and Class in the City that black solidarity
is practiced in the process of black gentrification of North
Kenwood-Oakland, a Chicago historically black neighborhood known for
its poverty. She asserts that despite the divergent class interests
of the recent influx of black middle-class homeowners and the
working-class residents, black solidarity is still the predominant
factor in political action due to the primacy of race as a unifying
factor of in the lives of black Americans and her belief that this
dialogue on race between newcomers and the poor is the process of
solidarity. Michael Hanchard and Stokely Carmichael, however, would
criticize her view on black solidarity as practiced in this southside
Chicago community. Both Hanchard and Carmichael would counter, due to
black gentrification’s contradictory results for the working-class
and poor that reproduces classism, white supremacy, and singular
notions of blackness, the black solidarity practiced in this case is
not real solidarity that can produce social change. Where Hanchard
and Carmichael disagree is in the role of race as a key component of
African American political action, since Carmichael’s nationalist
position emphasizes organizing among blacks before joining coalitions
while Hanchard notes the inevitable disunity and contradictions that
arise from focusing entirely on racial identity as a unifying force
due to the multiple identities an individual possesses
simultaneously.
Carmichael, who
sees the primary problem of black America as the double reality of
being poor and black and any political program for blacks must
acknowledge this duality, which black nationalism does as envisioned
by Carmichael. Although he would admire and respect the black
middle-class’s feelings of obligation to the black poor and the
belief in a linked fate that predominates among blacks of all
classes, since black unity across class is necessary to build
political and economic power within black communities, Carmichael
opposes the capitalist system which creates and reproduces the
unequal social conditions that constitute racism. His economic
philosophy of black nationalism embraces cooperatives under community
control rather than black bourgeoisie, which participates in the
white-dominated capitalist system. The black gentrification also
works against the economic interests of the black poor, represented
by the renters who rely on some form of public assistance to live in
the North Kenwood-Oakland area.1
Moreover, not all homeowners share the same economic background. The
older residents who have acquired homes lack the higher income of
professional, black gentry who cause property values to rise, hurting
retirees and older folks without the means to pay their rising
property taxes.2
Thus, even those with stable incomes and who own their homes find
their economic foothold challenged as a result of black
gentrification, which contradicts Carmichael’s belief that real
black economic nationalism would provide businesses and wealth
through cooperative means. For Carmichael, black power economically
means, “We want to see the cooperative concept applied in business
and banking...The society we seek to build among black people, then,
is not a capitalist one.”3
The persistence of economic injustice and absence of cooperative
businesses, housing, and rising property values, in addition to
measures taken by the black upper-classes to limit accessibility to
public housing demonstrate the lack of real black solidarity. The
poverty of blacks, who comprise a majority in this Chicago
neighborhood, must be addressed to be a move toward solidarity. The
larger issue of poverty remains unaddressed, despite the four
mechanisms that supposedly protect the interests of poor blacks. The
four mechanisms Pattillo describe that result from mixed-income
communities theoretically combat poverty by doing the following: 1.
establishing social networks across class that could lead to
employment or education, or other resources, 2. improve social
control by bringing order, strong management and eventually overall
safety, 3. provide a model of upward mobility for the poor, and 4.
bring increased political and economic attention to the
neighborhood.4
But the results of black middlemen fighting poverty have not improved
the conditions for most poor blacks. By clinging to a unity that
privileges race over class without recognizing the intersection of
poverty and race, the poor and longtime blacks of the neighborhood
suffer since these aforementioned social mechanisms have served the
anti-egalitarian interests of white capitalists and politicians.
Carmichael would
also criticize the practice of black solidarity in North
Kenwood-Oakland for its attempts to impose cultural assimilation on
lower-class residents. Black gentrification paradoxically supports
the imposition of middle-class white values. If one perceives
Patillo’s characterization of black solidarity as just an updated
version of DuBois’s Talented Tenth theory due to her belief in the
power of black middlemen, then the increasing class differentiation
of the neighborhood perpetuates elitism and middle-class values as
the normative for social behavior. Those who cannot act in accordance
with white middle-class values as practiced by the black middle-class
bear the brunt of black elites’ attempts to criminalize their
behavior and attacks on behavioral patterns, dress, and hairstyles.
One finds evidence of the black elites’ battles with the
working-class and poor by complaining about their barbecues on their
front lawns and public spaces, their littering, lack of attention to
middle-class standards of house decorum and how they repair cars in
the street.5
Carmichael proposed black nationalism based on democratic practices
and cooperative economics to reject the assumptions of white
supremacy inherent in assimilation. Carmichael’s example of black
children sent to white schools, or blacks moving into white
neighborhoods as part of this underlying assumption of integration,
which perpetuates whiteness as superior and blackness as inferior.6
In North Kenwood-Oakland, a perverse form develops that, though
blacks are returning to the ghettos, they continue to accept white
middle-class expectations of social behavior and morality, something
that takes the form of pernicious actions against the poor. For
example, new residents support screening of tenants of public
housing, which culminated in a ban on anyone with a criminal record.
This excludes an enormous amount of the working-class and poor since
approximately 55% of black men in Chicago have criminal records and
would not be allowed to live with relatives in the area.7
Clearly, the black middle-class’s claims to leadership in racial
uplift are grounded in, as Patillo herself indicates, white
middle-class notions of respectability: patriarchal family relations,
sexual conservatism, financial sobriety, reserved comportment and
intellectual achievement.8
These values reflect a class bias against lower-class blacks, who are
gradually eliminated from public space as the eradication of high
rise housing, screening of tenants, rising property values, and
heightened policing by University of Chicago police limit the numbers
of opportunities of using public space and living in the area.9
Hanchard, on the
other hand, would defend his critique of black gentrification and its
reliance on race as unifying factor by challenging the assumption of
race as a singular identity. As the class distinctions and battles
linked to class rage between the black upper-class and the
working-class, both sides reassert the primacy of race as a factor in
unity. However, as Hanchard demonstrates, using race as sole
criterion for political action and organizing inevitably excludes
some blacks, thereby ignoring the huge differences and multiple
identities every individual balances.10
Black nationalism, for instance, is limited by its reliance on race
as the sole identity for those perceived as black in society, thus
ignoring the role of gender, sexuality, class and multiracial
individuals whose oppression survives in masculinist, heteronormative
organizations. Pan-Africanism also failed for the similar reason of
assuming a monolithic blackness that ignored the unique experiences
of peoples of African descent throughout the world which vary
according to nationality, ethnicity, culture, and lived experience.11
As Hanchard himself elucidates, “By asking not “what are black
people” but instead, “what tends to happen to people defined as
black that does not happen with the same relative frequency to other
people in a given society,”12
one can develop a better basis for political action and solidarity
that challenges sexism, heternormativity, racism, poverty, and
attacks on the environment. For Hanchard, the only way black politics
can make long-lasting social change is to avoid racial essentialism,
which imposes a totalization of identity that ignores the
multiplicity of lived experience of those designated as black.
Chicago’s example of black gentrification displays this by the
persistence of class oppression and poverty.
Like Carmichael,
Hanchard would also criticize the class-based assault on social
behavior of the black poor. Due to competing notions of what
constitutes blackness, both the afrostocracy and urban poor express
their individual notions of blackness and their other identities in
various ways. The lower-classes may express themselves through
talking in Ebonics more often, barbecuing in front lawns, and
dressing more casually than black gentry, and the homeowners should
not dictate what comprises proper blackness for others. Moreover,
Hanchard’s theory of black politics emphasizes coalitions, since,
“The creation of political community necessarily entails more than
recognizing a problem or phenomena, such as racism. It encompasses
the combination of ideas, peoples, and practices mobilized in
response to a set of circumstances that involves other political
communities, peoples, and institutions.”13
Without real coalitions that connect those at the bottom of the
income scale to others outside of the neighborhood, beyond
neighboring black middle-class residents, the ability of the black
community to affect societal change by achieving redistributive
economic policies is severely limited. Pattillo’s text does not
elucidate how black gentrification will connect poor and
working-class blacks to broad coalitions that share the same goals of
economic and social justice. In fact, the black homeowners seem more
concerned with protecting their investments than economic
redistribution, though they also wish to dismantle racism.
Unfortunately, their economic interests tie them with white elites in
Chicago’s economic and political spheres, therefore they are unable
to provide less fortunate blacks with a broad coalition that must
include poor whites and others who share the same goal. Even
Carmichael also agrees that the best type of coalition to develop and
fundamentally change the nature of American politics is a coalition
between the poor blacks and poor whites.14
As a consequence, the notion of a singular blackness that ignores the
salience of class, gender and other identities limits the
effectiveness of using race as sole criterion for a political
community.
Another detrimental
flaw of the political community built through black gentrification
and using race as primary source for political action is the loss of
politicizing social spheres. Hanchard identifies a source of black
political action in its emphasis on politicizing social spaces due to
the formal exclusion of blacks from politics after Reconstruction.15
For example, during the Civil Rights Movement, blacks politicized the
social arena through sit-ins at lunch counters, boycotts, and music,
effectively polarizing the nation to aid the attempts to end
segregation through formal political practices, such as the black
vote in the North. The current practice of black politicking lacks
this social dimension since formal politics takes precedence through
black middle-class relations with white developers and politicians in
Chicago’s city politics. This loss of politicization of social
spaces excludes lower-class blacks from the black coalition’s
ability to enact social change for multiple reasons. First, low
income residents are silenced in community meetings or outnumbered by
black middle-class, who can afford to devote more of their time to
neighborhood associations.16
Those less fortunate individuals without the time and funds to attend
neighborhood meetings consequently lose one of their spaces to
address their own socioeconomic needs. The black gentry also
contradict the aims of racial uplift by their dominance of relations
to whites in the political and economic systems, since they work with
these formal spaces of politics in a way that hurts the interests of
working-class residents in housing, economics, and policing. Their
ability to express themselves and act in their own interests in
neighborhood meetings and on the street is limited by attempts to
curtail their individuality and behavior, which are seen as causes of
poverty to some of the black middle-class.
For most blacks,
the persistence of racism makes race one of unifying factors in black
politics. However, as both Carmichael and Hanchard would concur,
black political action that emphasizes race ignores prioritizing the
class interests of the poor that transcend race. Black gentrification
of North Kenwood-Oakland has failed to bring redistributive economic
justice and build a stronger, black community built on cooperative
economics, preferred by Carmichael’s characterization of black
nationalism. Hanchard criticizes black political theory that
emphasizes solely race without acknowledging the multiple identities
and problems facing blacks. By clinging to a notion of race-based
solidarity that neglects the divergent class interests of blacks, the
people of North Kenwood-Oakland actually perpetuate social inequities
that occurred as a result of racism. Although it is tempting to
privilege race as the key factor of black politics due to the
preservation of racism in America, Hanchard correctly notes that
black political organizers should focus on “what tends to happen to
people defined as black that does not happen with the same relative
frequency to other people in a given society.”17
Black nationalist Carmichael would only agree in that black
solidarity as practiced by the people of North Kenwood-Oakland is
limited by ignoring the class-based oppression of blacks, which can
occur under blacks or whites, regardless of who is gentrifying the
neighborhood.
Bibliography
Stokely Carmichael,
“What We Want,” September 22, 1966.
Michael Hanchard,
“The Contours of Black Political Thought: An Introduction and
Perspective,” Political Theory, 38, No. 4 (2010).
Mary Patillo, Black
on the Block: The Politics of Race and Class in the City (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2007).
1
Mary Pattillo, Black on the Block: The Politics of Race and Class
in the City (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007): 14.
2
Ibid.
3
Stokely Carmichael, “What We Want”: 6-7.
4
Mary Pattillo, Black on the Block: The Politics of Race and Class in
the City (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007): 109.
5
Ibid., 15.
6
Stokely Carmichael, “What We Want”: 4.
7
Mary Pattillo, Black on the Block: The Politics of Race and Class
in the City (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007): 282.
8
Ibid., 104.
9
Ibid., 286.
10
Michael Hanchard, “The Contours of Black Political Thought: An
Introduction and Perspective,” 524.
11
Ibid., 527.
12
Ibid., 529.
13
Ibid, 525.
14
Stokely Carmichael, “What We Want”: 6.
15
Michael Hanchard, “The Contours of Black Political Thought: An
Introduction and Perspective,” 520.
16
Mary Pattillo, Black on the Block: The Politics of Race and Class in
the City (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007): 15.
17
Michael Hanchard, “The Contours of Black Political Thought: An
Introduction and Perspective,” 529.
After writing this essay, which viewpoint did you come to respect more? It seems to me Carmichael doesn't go far enough. Racial essentialism is the problem. Promoting essentialism, even in the form of pan-africanism or black nationalism, is counter productive.
ReplyDeleteI agree racial essentialism is the problem, but there are strains of black nationalism which could possibly evade that. I believe Tommie Shelby's We Who Are Dark: The Philosophical Foundations of Black Solidarity explains this suitably but at that point it may be best to not define it as 'black nationalism.' So I guess I'm more in agreement with Hanchard overall.
ReplyDeleteThanks for the recommendation. Never heard of Tommie Shelby, but the book looks interesting. Perhaps a way to curb the excesses of Hanchard's strategy - if there's no kind of solidarity, and all that's left is a "fuck you, I got mine" mindset, you risk splitting the vote, dividing the effort, and turning people against each other. There's strength in numbers. No one should organize around an imaginary shared identity. But you gotta organize around something.
ReplyDelete